GLORIA

GEOMAR Library Ocean Research Information Access

Your email was sent successfully. Check your inbox.

An error occurred while sending the email. Please try again.

Proceed reservation?

Export
  • 1
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Cambridge University Press (CUP) ; 1947
    In:  Journal of Symbolic Logic Vol. 12, No. 4 ( 1947-12), p. 130-132
    In: Journal of Symbolic Logic, Cambridge University Press (CUP), Vol. 12, No. 4 ( 1947-12), p. 130-132
    Abstract: In his Mathematical logic Quine characterizes the theorems of quantification theory by six principles:
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0022-4812 , 1943-5886
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Cambridge University Press (CUP)
    Publication Date: 1947
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 2010607-5
    SSG: 5,1
    SSG: 17,1
    Location Call Number Limitation Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
  • 2
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Cambridge University Press (CUP) ; 1950
    In:  Journal of Symbolic Logic Vol. 15, No. 4 ( 1950-12), p. 241-247
    In: Journal of Symbolic Logic, Cambridge University Press (CUP), Vol. 15, No. 4 ( 1950-12), p. 241-247
    Abstract: In [1] we have considered a certain system L and shown that although its axioms are considerably weaker than those of [2], it suffices for purposes of the topics covered in [2] . The purpose of the present paper is to consider the system L more carefully and to show that with suitably chosen definitions for numbers, the ordinary theory of real numbers is also obtainable in it. For this purpose, we shall indicate that we can prove in L a certain set of twenty axioms used by Tarski which are sufficient for the arithmetic of real numbers and are to the effect that real numbers form a complete ordered field. Indeed, we cannot prove in L all Tarski's twenty axioms in their full generality. One of them, stating in effect that every bounded class of real numbers possesses a least upper bound, can only be proved as a metatheorem which states that every bounded nameable class of real numbers possesses a least upper bound. However, all the other nineteen axioms can be proved in L without any modification. This result may be of some interest because the axioms of L are considerably weaker than those commonly employed for the same purpose. In L variables need to take as values only classes each of whose members has no more than two members. In other words, only classes each with no more than two members are to be elements. On the other hand, it is usual to assume for the purpose of natural arithmetic that all finite classes are elements, and, for the purpose of real arithmetic, that all enumerable classes are elements.
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0022-4812 , 1943-5886
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Cambridge University Press (CUP)
    Publication Date: 1950
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 2010607-5
    SSG: 5,1
    SSG: 17,1
    Location Call Number Limitation Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
  • 3
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Cambridge University Press (CUP) ; 1953
    In:  Journal of Symbolic Logic Vol. 18, No. 2 ( 1953-06), p. 180-181
    In: Journal of Symbolic Logic, Cambridge University Press (CUP), Vol. 18, No. 2 ( 1953-06), p. 180-181
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0022-4812 , 1943-5886
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Cambridge University Press (CUP)
    Publication Date: 1953
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 2010607-5
    SSG: 5,1
    SSG: 17,1
    Location Call Number Limitation Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
  • 4
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Cambridge University Press (CUP) ; 1957
    In:  Journal of Symbolic Logic Vol. 22, No. 2 ( 1957-06), p. 145-158
    In: Journal of Symbolic Logic, Cambridge University Press (CUP), Vol. 22, No. 2 ( 1957-06), p. 145-158
    Abstract: I once asked myself the question: How were the famous axiom systems, such as Euclid's for geometry, Zermelo's for set theory, Peano's for arithmetic, originally obtained? This was to me more than merely a historical question, as I wished to know how the basic concepts and axioms were to be singled out, and, once they were singled out, how one could establish their adequacy. One possible approach which suggests itself is to take typical theorems, proofs, definitions, and examine case by case what assumptions and concepts are involved. The obstacle in such an empirical study is, apart from the obvious demand of excessive time and energy, the lack of conclusiveness in both result and justification. The attempt to find an answer to this question led me to some interesting fragments of history. For example, in 1899 Cantor distinguished consistent collections (the “sets”) from inconsistent collections ([1], p. 443), anticipating partly the distinction between the two kinds of classes stressed by von Neumann and Quine. Cantor had already proposed a form of the axiom of substitution ([1] , p. 444, line 3), although Fraenkel and Skolem, more than twenty years later, had to adjoin it to Zermelo's list of axioms as a supplement. In another direction, the history of the development of axioms of geometry makes clear how natural it was for Hilbert to raise in 1900 the consistency question of analysis ([2] , p. 299) quite independently of the emphasis on set-theoretical paradoxes. By far the best piece of good fortune I had in these historical researches was, however, my findings with regard to Peano's axioms for arithmetic. It is rather well-known, through Peano's own acknowledgement ([3], p. 273), that Peano borrowed his axioms from Dedekind and made extensive use of Grassmann's work in his development of the axioms.
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0022-4812 , 1943-5886
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Cambridge University Press (CUP)
    Publication Date: 1957
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 2010607-5
    SSG: 5,1
    SSG: 17,1
    Location Call Number Limitation Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
  • 5
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Cambridge University Press (CUP) ; 1951
    In:  Journal of Symbolic Logic Vol. 16, No. 4 ( 1951-12), p. 302-303
    In: Journal of Symbolic Logic, Cambridge University Press (CUP), Vol. 16, No. 4 ( 1951-12), p. 302-303
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0022-4812 , 1943-5886
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Cambridge University Press (CUP)
    Publication Date: 1951
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 2010607-5
    SSG: 5,1
    SSG: 17,1
    Location Call Number Limitation Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
  • 6
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Cambridge University Press (CUP) ; 1950
    In:  Journal of Symbolic Logic Vol. 15, No. 2 ( 1950-06), p. 103-112
    In: Journal of Symbolic Logic, Cambridge University Press (CUP), Vol. 15, No. 2 ( 1950-06), p. 103-112
    Abstract: In mathematics, when we want to introduce classes which fulfill certain conditions, we usually prove beforehand that classes fulfilling such conditions do exist, and that such classes are uniquely determined by the conditions. The statements which state such unicity and existence of classes are in mathematical logic consequences of the principles of extensionality and class existence. In order to illustrate how these principles enable us to introduce classes into systems of mathematical logic, let us consider the manner in which Gödel introduces classes in his book on set theory. For instance, before introducing the definition of the non-ordered pair of two classes Gödel puts down as its justification the following two axioms: By A4, for every two classes y and z there exists at least one non-ordered pair w of them; and by A3, w is uniquely determined in A4.
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0022-4812 , 1943-5886
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Cambridge University Press (CUP)
    Publication Date: 1950
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 2010607-5
    SSG: 5,1
    SSG: 17,1
    Location Call Number Limitation Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
  • 7
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Cambridge University Press (CUP) ; 1952
    In:  Journal of Symbolic Logic Vol. 17, No. 2 ( 1952-06), p. 105-116
    In: Journal of Symbolic Logic, Cambridge University Press (CUP), Vol. 17, No. 2 ( 1952-06), p. 105-116
    Abstract: Certain axiomatic systems involve more than one category of fundamental objects; for example, points, lines, and planes in geometry; individuals, classes of individuals, etc. in the theory of types or in predicate calculi of orders higher than one. It is natural to use variables of different kinds with their ranges respectively restricted to different categories of objects, and to assume as substructure the usual quantification theory (the restricted predicate calculus) for each of the various kinds of variables together with the usual theory of truth functions for the formulas of the system. An axiomatic theory set up in this manner will be called many-sorted. We shall refer to the theory of truth functions and quantifiers in it as its (many-sorted) elementary logic, and call the primitive symbols and axioms (including axiom schemata) the proper primitive symbols and proper axioms of the system. Our purpose in this paper is to investigate the many-sorted systems and their elementary logics. Among the proper primitive symbols of a many-sorted system T n ( n = 2, …, ω ) there may be included symbols of some or all of the following kinds: (1) predicates denoting the properties and relations treated in the system; (2) functors denoting the functions treated in the system; (3) constant names for certain objects of the system. We may either take as primitive or define a predicate denoting the identity relation in T n .
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0022-4812 , 1943-5886
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Cambridge University Press (CUP)
    Publication Date: 1952
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 2010607-5
    SSG: 5,1
    SSG: 17,1
    Location Call Number Limitation Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
  • 8
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Cambridge University Press (CUP) ; 1948
    In:  Journal of Symbolic Logic Vol. 13, No. 4 ( 1948-12), p. 215-216
    In: Journal of Symbolic Logic, Cambridge University Press (CUP), Vol. 13, No. 4 ( 1948-12), p. 215-216
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0022-4812 , 1943-5886
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Cambridge University Press (CUP)
    Publication Date: 1948
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 2010607-5
    SSG: 5,1
    SSG: 17,1
    Location Call Number Limitation Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
  • 9
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Philosophy Documentation Center ; 1947
    In:  The Journal of Philosophy Vol. 44, No. 26 ( 1947-12-18), p. 701-
    In: The Journal of Philosophy, Philosophy Documentation Center, Vol. 44, No. 26 ( 1947-12-18), p. 701-
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0022-362X
    RVK:
    Language: Unknown
    Publisher: Philosophy Documentation Center
    Publication Date: 1947
    SSG: 5,1
    Location Call Number Limitation Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
  • 10
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Oxford University Press (OUP) ; 1948
    In:  Mind Vol. LVII, No. 228 ( 1948), p. 488-490
    In: Mind, Oxford University Press (OUP), Vol. LVII, No. 228 ( 1948), p. 488-490
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0026-4423 , 1460-2113
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Oxford University Press (OUP)
    Publication Date: 1948
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 1478974-7
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 3513-0
    SSG: 5,1
    SSG: 5,2
    Location Call Number Limitation Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
Close ⊗
This website uses cookies and the analysis tool Matomo. More information can be found here...